Page 1 of 20

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal – Vol. 10, No. 1

Publication Date: January 25, 2023

DOI:10.14738/assrj.101.13896.

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A

Transdisciplinary and Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship:

Towards A Transdisciplinary and Transcultural Approach

Enrico Facco

Studium Patavinum, Dept. of Neurosciences,

University of Padua, Italy, and Inst. Franco Granone,

Italian Center of Clinical & Experimental Hypnosis, Turin, Italy

Fabio Fracas

University of Padua, Italy, and

Scientific Collaboration Manager, Transmutex, Geneve, Swiss

Silvano Tagliagambe

University of Sassari, Italy

ABSTRACT

The aim of this paper is to overview the main epistemological implications of the

scientific approach to consciousness and the mind-brain relationship, undergone a

lively debate in the past decades by strict materialist monist and dualist stances.

Their limits, as well as the limits of reductionism and the shortcomings of classical

Western thought, suggest the need for a broader perspective. Actually, a

transdisciplinary approach helps overcoming the limits and incompleteness of

single axiomatic disciplines. Likewise, a transcultural, meta philosophical

approach allows to understand key concepts and meanings common to

different philosophies and cultures and properly face them beyond the

multiplicity and ostensible oddity of forms. This approach seems to be

appropriate in the study of consciousness and subjective phenomena, where

the first-person perspective and the meaning of the experience are the condition

sine qua non for their comprehension.

Keywords: consciousness, epistemology, materialism, dualism, metaphilosophy,

metascience

INTRODUCTION

The reflections on the nature of consciousness and soul date back to the beginning of

philosophy in both the East and the West. The term consciousness has a wide range of

meanings, like all terms related to subjective phenomena; as a result, albeit appearing familiar

and conceptually clear, it can hardly be restricted in a comprehensive, simple definition. In fact,

in the history of philosophy, the concept of consciousness greatly overlapped with that of soul

and ego, while in the post-Cartesian thought, they were assigned a different ontology with

respect to the physical reality, leading to their irreconcilable separation and

incommensurability. According to Jaynes, consciousness is also diachronic − i.e., it cannot be

properly comprehended outside history and culture [1,2].

Page 2 of 20

415

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

Actually, the foundation of the science of consciousness has involved huge epistemological and

metaphysical issues that have been mainly faced in a lively, still ongoing debate between

materialist monist and dualist stances [3,4], the key point of which has been well defined by

Chalmers in terms of easy problem and hard problem [5,6]. A proper comprehension of

consciousness, especially the hard problem and the relationship between the inner and outer

world, inescapably involves a broader perspective encompassing transdisciplinary and

transcultural aspects in order to exceed the limits of the classic materialist and dualist

interpretations.

The aim of this article is to outline the reasons for such an approach. It is a broad topic that

cannot be analyzed in all details within the space of an article; nevertheless, an overview of its

main aspects may provide some food for further thought, hopefully stimulating deeper analysis

in each specific theme without losing track of the topic as a whole and the close connection

between its components.

ON THE SCIENCE OF CONSCIOUSNESS: EPISTEMOLOGICAL IMPLICATIONS

Medicine has a central role in defining the boundaries between health and disease;

nevertheless, the definition of disorders is a hard job endowed with profound cultural and

epistemological implications and a relevant risk of misdiagnosis, especially when psychological

and psychiatric disorders are concerned [7–9]. Furthermore, a variety of anomalous, ostensibly

odd experiences, named Non-Ordinary Mental expressions (NOMEs), are non-pathological in

nature and call for being properly understood rather than psychiatrized [10]. NOMEs are an

inescapable aspect of consciousness, as well defined by William James:

“It is that our normal waking consciousness, rational consciousness as we call it, is

but one special type of consciousness, whilst all about it, parted from it by the

filmiest of screens, there lie potential forms of consciousness entirely different. We

may go through life without suspecting their existence; but apply the requisite

stimulus, and at a touch, they are there in all their completeness, definite types of

mentality which probably somewhere have their field of application and

adaptation. No account of the universe in its totality can be final, which leaves these

other forms of consciousness quite disregarded” (11, p. 111).

By definition, consciousness is an irreducibly subjective phenomenon, the contents of which

can only be known by inner perception and shared with others through communication of the

experience by first- and second-person perspective (1PP and 2PP, respectively); furthermore,

some essential aspects of the Self may be approached by introspection only [12]. Qualia − the

phenomenological properties of sense data, including perceptual experiences, bodily

sensations, felt reactions, passions or emotions, and felt moods [13] − are of crucial importance

in the comprehension of consciousness, raising a lively debate between physicalists and anti- physicalists in the past decades and leading to several, still unsolved mental experiments (e.g.,

the zombie) being introduced [14–16].

Furthermore, phenomenal experiences and cognition include both unconscious and conscious

levels in an unceasing reciprocal exchange of information, ranging from anoetic to noetic ones,

up to the level of self-reflexive experiences [17]. The transition from anoetic to noetic

Page 3 of 20

416

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

experiences reflects a caudo-rostral integration in the brain. The latter dresses the former with

images, concepts, and metaphors to be consciously experienced and make them meaningful and

communicable. Their essential feature is their meaning, despite quantitative aspects of

perception being also relevant; for example, pain is an exclusively subjective experience

featured by well-known specific quality and intensity. Its unpleasantness and meaning deeply

affect its intensity and tolerability [18].

The foundation of the science of consciousness has entailed a huge debate between materialist

monists, considering it as a plain epiphenomenon of brain circuits, and those considered as

dualists, who think that consciousness and qualia cannot be reduced to brain circuitry. Some

authors have hypothesized an unbridgeable explanatory gap between brain circuitry and

consciousness, leading to physicalist claims being falsified due to the lack of entailment

between them [6,19]. As a result, the gap would call for bridge laws able to properly connect

the reduced theory to the reducing one. On the other hand, other authors think that a

conceptual gap does not necessarily entail an explanatory gap and that the problem can be

solved by theoretical identifications [20] or, anyway, bridge laws are not necessary at all [21].

Nevertheless, Marras has supported his argument pro theoretical identification with the

example of pain, as follows [20]:

For once we have got our theoretical identifications (inductively derived as they

must be), it can’t any longer be a mystery why C-fibers firing should feel like pain:

C-fiber firing is pain; and it is a mystery that pain should feel like pain? As Kim

earlier remarked, ‘Identity takes away the logical space in which explanatory

questions can be formulated’” (Italics in the original text).

Unfortunately for physicalists, pain is a very complex functional phenomenon that cannot be

equated to C-fiber firing. In fact, the universally accepted definition of pain defines it as an

unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage

or described in terms of such damage [22,23]. This definition clearly states that pain is a matter

of sensory and emotional experience and properly avoids tying it to nervous pathways

stimulation. This is tantamount to saying, “no experience, no pain”, implying that pain may be

managed not only by pain killers but also by changing the experience. An outstanding proof is

hypnotic analgesia, which may be as effective as to significantly relieve chronic pain and even

allow for surgery without anesthetic drugs [24,25]. In fact, hypnosis is the result of an

intentional, introspective activity leading to the pain neuro matrix in the brain being controlled

and inputs from C-fibers to the somatosensory cortex being blocked [26]: thus, a maximal

stimulation of C-fibers in the periphery may not be equivalent to even the slightest pain. This

also shows the self-contradictory overriding attitude of the reductionist approach of medicine

to pain, mainly relying on a bottom-up pharmacological manipulation of nociception while

neglecting a top-down change of the experience [18].

The example of pain has also been used in the argument of truth-makers of perceived inner

states [27], though in a questionable way (for criticism, see [12]). Pain is not a plain symptom

of physical damage. Rather, it is the suffering of the individual as a whole, a fact entailing huge

psychological and existential implications that cannot be ignored in clinical practice. Le Breton

Page 4 of 20

417

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

has wisely defined pain as an incision of the sacred, ripping one from himself and leading to

face one’s limits, the transience of life and its cost: thus, pain obliges to metaphysics [28,29].

The explanatory gap between brain circuitry and experience also depends on the brain

incalculable complexity, plasticity, and unceasing transformation over the life span. It is the

condition at the basis of the development of human consciousness in a ceaseless exchange of

information with the unconscious and the outer world, making every human being a unique

individual entity. As a result, this complex uniqueness, together with the definition of

consciousness as an emergent property, make it difficult to analyze it in a discrete or

parsimonious manner even when its reduction is in principle admitted [30].

The debate on reductionism in the philosophy of mind includes the problem of reliability of

measures of introspective activity, the uncertainty of which has led Elizabeth Irvine to wonder

whether it is a methodological muddle to be abandoned or even calling for withdrawing

consciousness from scientific practice [31,32]. The problem is far from being new and has

undergone a deep analysis in the past centuries in both Eastern and Western philosophies. It is

well-known that introspection may be self-deceptive, given that the observer has a restricted

perception of his/her inner world (ignoring all that is unconscious) and may alter the

observation of inner states. On the other hand, the validity of perception and understanding of

the outer world is far from being unerring − as the very history of science clearly shows − a fact

reflecting the more general evidence of human fallibility in the process of knowledge as a whole

At any rate, behavioral measurements, despite being useful, are not enough, and the knowledge

of introspective data remains essential for an appropriate comprehension of experience, self- perception, self-awareness, and self-knowledge. Furthermore, the only way to hopefully

recognize self-deception is through metacognition, which remains a matter of introspection,

inner third-person perspective, and critical analysis [12].

Given qualia’s subjective, qualitative nature, Galilean sciences (bonr to investigate the physical

world only) cannot properly investigate and understand them. In this regard, it is worth noting

that their distinction between primary (e.g., shape, size, position, stillness and movement) and

secondary qualities (e.g., colors, smell, taste, sound) was introduced by Democritus first, who

denied qualities other than shape and size belonging to the atoms themselves. However, he

stated that,

“There are two kinds of knowledge, one genuine, one bastard (or ‘obscure’). To the

former belong all the following: sight, hearing, smell, taste, touch” (Fragment

DK68B11).

The Democritus’ definition of senses was uncritically adopted by Galileo and Descartes, leading

them to believe that primary qualities, unlike secondary ones, were an objective property of

things compatible with the mathematical model − a distinction supported by their

mathematical apriorism [33] – and the assumption that reality could be objectively known as it

is, an assumption not without an element degree of naïve realism. Therefore, the distinction

between primary and secondary qualities remains questionable since they are similar as

concerns both their neurocorrelates and the relationship observer/observed phenomenon.

Page 5 of 20

418

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

HISTORICAL-PHILOSOPHICAL IMPLICATIONS

Given all this, a short discussion of a few essential aspects of the history of philosophy, science,

and medicine may help envisioning some crucial questions involved in the scientific approach

to consciousness [the topic has been discussed in more detail elsewhere [3,34].

Ancient Greek culture was an inseparable blend of rational philosophy and mysteric doctrines,

including oracles and initiation rites, all great personalities (including Plato and Aristotle) were

admitted to. Likewise, medicine was intimately connected to the sacred for over 3,000 years,

from Imhotep temples in ancient Egypt to Asclepius temples-hospitals in Greece, where

incubation (to be considered as a form of proto-hypnosis) was used together with drugs and

surgery as an inseparable part of a psychosomatic approach [35]. Hippocrates has been the

most outstanding Greek physician introducing the rational approach (loghismós) and rightfully

considered the great father of modern medicine. The paradigm brought by both Hippocrates

and Parmenides contemplated the reality with a non-dualist perspective holding the

inseparability of the whole (ὅλης φύσεως, hólēs physeos), the complementarity of opposites,

and the concept of δύναμις (dynamis, power), a paradigm akin to Taoism1 and traditional

Chinese medicine.

The concept of dynamis, definable as the inseparable, dynamic interrelationship of mind-brain- body-environment, is a surprisingly modern intuition of complex systems, a topic only recently

introduced in medicine and biology [36,37]. The theory of complexity is a topic of paramount

importance in physics as well, recently earning Hasselman, Manabe, and Parisi the Nobel Prize

[38]. Besides spin glasses [39,40], the theory may be applied to life sciences, such as proteins

dynamics, DNA, learning and behavior [41,42]. Therefore, living beings might be better

understood taking a holistic approach and the theory of complexity in due account.

The scientific revolution of the 17th Century has been the cornerstone of the rational knowledge

of the physical world in Western culture. Nevertheless, it was not born of a free epistemological

reflection; instead, it depended on a political compromise with the Church, claiming its

exclusive competence on the soul. This resulted into what has been previously named the

original sin of Galilean sciences[3,43]. Therefore, the split between medicine and religion is only

a relatively recent phenomenon restricted to the Western friction between Galilean Sciences

and the Church (only a close-minded socio-political question, the meaning of religion should

not be mistaken with2). Descartes, strongly concerned about avoiding an irreconcilable conflict

with the Church, assigned different ontologies to the res cogitans and res extensa, making them

scientifically incommensurable − a sort of loophole allowing for the compromise with the

Church, obtained at the cost of splitting what in nature was inseparably interconnected. The

solution was a dualist political parceling, assigning the soul (consciousness) to the Church and

the physical world plus the earthen body machine to the science, safe from the Inquisition. The

Descartes’ errors have not been considered worthy of revision until recent years [3,44], while

the science of consciousness was born in the 1980s’ (i.e., over three centuries after the political

1 There is a clear concordance between the Parmenides’ concept of Being and Tao, as well as between his Light- Dark and the concept of Yin-Yang [12,50].

2 The etymology and meaning of the term religion, also calling for a metareligious approach, has been described

elsewhere [3,35].

Page 6 of 20

419

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

compromise with the Church) as a long-term result of a strong cultural filter preventing one to

deal with it.

Then, Western rationalism and Cartesianism moved towards Positivism and materialist

monism – the mainstream science is based on; the latter can be founded only when an

autonomous, independent ontology of matter is metaphysically adopted and, in this regard, it

can be considered as a long-term result of the Cartesian split. However, materialist monism is

metaphysically self-contradictory, in that it a priori rejects what looks to be immaterial

(consciousness) without demonstrating its inexistence − the Ryle’s metaphor of the phantom in

the machine [45] − implicitly admitting it to allow for its refusal. Furthermore, it relies on

“observed” facts and assertions belonging themselves to the refused reality of mental products

[34,46].

Galileo himself accepted the limitation of science to the physical world reluctantly. Has he

stated in his Dialogue Concerning the Two New Sciences (Day 3, corollary 3) [47],

“We must be satisfied to belong to that class of less worthy workmen who procure

from the quarry the marble out of which, later, the gifted sculptor [the theologian;

authors’ note] produces those masterpieces which lay hidden in this rough and

shapeless exterior”.

However, his mathematical apriorism was outstanding and successful in the investigation of

the physical world. On the other hand, its exclusive use in living beings is questionable, in that

it reduces them to a set of equivalent quantitative mathematical parameters only, as well

pictured by Florenskji:

“The rationalistic understanding of life does not distinguish, and is not able to

distinguish, between a person and a thing. More precisely, it has only one category,

the category of thingness, and therefore all things, including persons, are reified by

this understanding, are taken as a thing, as res.” [48].

In this cultural climate, medicine focused more and more on the Cartesian bodily earthen

machine only, reducing human beings to a sort of small clocks [e.g., the Machine Man [49]]

immersed in the big clock of a deterministic Newtonian universe. The resulting mechanist- reductionist stance neglecting the soul has inadvertently led to Hippocrates’ teaching being

betrayed [50]. As a result, the undeniable power and effectiveness of modern scientific

medicine shows its limits in front of subjectivity, which is the inescapable core of psychological

and psychosomatic disorders, suffering, pain, distress, and the existential implications of severe

diseases − i.e., the specter of disability and the perception of one’s doom [51].

The Principle of the Nonoverlapping Magisteria [52] − held by Pope Pius XII in his encyclical

Humani Generis (1950) − can be considered as the long-term result of the forced compromise

between the new sciences and the Church in the 17th Century. It has also been endorsed by the

National Academy of Sciences of the USA:

Page 7 of 20

420

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

“Many scientists are deeply religious. But science and religion occupy two separate

realms of human experience. Demanding that they be combined detracts from the

glory of each” [53].

Gould himself recognized the limits of the Principle of Nonoverlapping Magisteria [52]:

“This resolution might remain all neat and clean if the nonoverlapping magisteria

of science and religion were separated by an extensive no man’s land ... In fact, the

two magisteria bump right up against each other, interdigitating in wondrously

complex ways along their joint border. Many of our deepest questions call upon

aspects of both for different parts of a full answer”.

Hence, the Principle of Nonoverlapping Magisteria remains a mediocre political compromise

rather than a solid, epistemologically well-founded principle. It is constitutively unable to

properly solve the huge problems rising at the surface of friction between science and religion

(or better, the Church), a fact occurring in clinical practice when facing the above-mentioned

conditions and NOMEs, like Mystical and Near-Death Experiences [43,54–57] with their vast

philosophical-existential implications. Furthermore, they cannot be solved within the limits of

scientific reductionism, being it constitutively blind to subjectivity. At the same time, patient

care cannot be reduced to a set of mechanic interventions on the earthen body machine only.

The Mind-Brain Relationship Between Reductionism and Emergentism

Two key concepts define consciousness and the mind-brain relationship in neurosciences:

a) Consciousness as an emergent property of brain complexity;

b) The axiom that any mental state, process, and product is associated with specific

neurocorrelates.

Granted these concepts, no activity of mind and consciousness may occur without activating

the corresponding brain circuits. There is no problem in accepting it, but the correlation is not

synonymous of causality. As the concept of emergent property is concerned, it is a feature of

complex systems, implying the appearance of supervening properties, leading to the fallacy of

division and reduction. The case of consciousness is the most intriguing since there is no area

of consciousness in the brain. Rather, it emerges as a complex interrelationship of many, still

little defined areas and circuits, where the interface and transduction between brain circuitry

and the related mental events with their qualia (how they turn into each other) are unknown.

The mind-brain relationship may only establish their correlation: turning it into a bottom-up

exclusive causality is not logically allowed, while a bidirectional bottom-up and top-down

causation is more plausible. Indeed, a wealth of studies on hypnosis and meditation clearly

shows how the mind may yield intentional activations/deactivation of unconscious brain areas

through introspection, leading one to achieve outstanding goals, one for all the above- mentioned hypnotic analgesia [26,58,59].

Page 8 of 20

421

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

If the above discussion is correct, one should refrain from adopting an inflexible axiomatic

stance − be it materialist or not, reductionist or anti-reductionist, or anything else − and a priori

projecting ethnocentric and anthropocentric prejudices, axioms, and mental categories into the

outer world with the illusion of knowing it “objectively”. Instead, the proper way to knowledge

should follow the exemplary concept of Russell’s enlargement of the Self [12, quoted by 60].

Reductionism remains a powerful and effective tool to investigate the causal relationship

between physical events; a crucial error is turning it into a sort of ontology, claiming its absolute

value and a priori rejecting anything ostensibly incompatible with it.

As far as objectivity is concerned, it is worth recalling that the perception of reality is weaker

than commonly believed, for the available information is necessarily partial, while the features

of sense organs (with their filters) and brain coding processes are unconscious, leading to naïve

realism (i.e., the belief that the senses provide us with direct awareness of objects as they

“really” are). If this is the case, the debate between realists and idealists seems flimsy for both

physical and subjective aspects form an inseparable whole in the interpretation of reality,

where everything belonging to the materialist view is made of mind-stuff, and the so-called

objectivity cannot trespass the level of shared Weltbild. Hence, the outer world, as it is known,

is an inseparable co-creation of the physical world (unknowable as it is in itself) and mind [34].

About Reductionism, Metaphysics, and Blindsight

According to van Riel and Gulick, reductionism is ontologically neutral in itself [61]; therefore,

it might be applied to seemingly nonphysical aspects of the world as well. If this is the case, even

idealism and Berkeley’s immaterialism might be regarded as forms of reduction from matter to

mind. The difference between materialists and idealists is in what has been axiomatically

adopted as the primary manifestation of reality (matter or mind, respectively). According to

Popper, materialist reductionism is an example of a “bad ad hoc reduction” in that it claims a

reduction of the mental to the physical on an a priori basis entailing an undue neglect of the

mind-body relationship [62].

Pain has also been used to explain the concept of reduction, as Ernest Nagel did with the

example of headache (Nagel, 1961; quoted by van Riel & Van Gulick, 2019). Indeed, the

definition of headache in neurology establishes that migraine is a complex neurovascular

disorder including genetic, neurophysiological, and neurochemical causes, and anatomical and

physiological features [64]. This is undoubtedly true but conditioned by the reductionist stance

skipping psychological and psychosomatic components: it remains a partial though valuable

view and, as such, not enough for proper comprehension and management. In fact, both

acupuncture and hypnosis have proved to be effective in its treatment [65,66], while 66% of

the effects of CGRP Antibodies − the newest high-cost drug for migraine prophylaxis − depend

on placebo response [67].

The idea that any psychological and biological phenomenon may be explained by disclosing its

most basic physical mechanisms is questionable if one considers that all living beings and

Nature itself are complex systems and, as such, are endowed with emergent properties and

capacity for adaptation and self-transformation. The fact that an emergent property of a system

is a feature of the system as a whole rather than its components poses legitimate doubts about

the reductionist claims of plain reducibility of living beings to their basic physical mechanisms

Page 9 of 20

422

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

and consciousness to brain circuitry. It also poses legitimate doubts about the appropriateness

of the prevailing deterministic inclination of medicine to what may show chaotic, unpredictable

behaviors as well as ceaseless self-transformation and self-organization in the dynamic

relationship with the environment [36,37,68–71]. Indeed, the most outstanding event showing

the inseparable dynamic interrelationship between animals, humans, viruses, and the

environment as parts of a non-determinist self-transforming complex system is the recent

COVID-19 pandemic.

In this context it is worth clarifying that the authors are neither reductionists nor anti- reductionists. Reductionism is a powerful method allowing for valuable knowledge of causal

relationships between facts and mechanisms at their base. But it is only a method to be used

when appropriate, and one should refrain from turning it into ontology, a stance prone to

dogmatic drifts.

The Century-old dispute between opposite metaphysical standpoints (e.g., materialist monism

vs. dualism) reflects their intrinsic limits, being each of them based on partial though plausible

metaphysical principles. Their ostensible incompatibility also stems from the Western logical

strategy of reasoning based on Aristoteles’ tripartite logic. Here, it is worth mentioning that the

principle of non-contradiction has never been demonstrated and is self-contradictory over

time; furthermore, it has been dismantled by quantum physics, demonstrating the photon’s

dual nature particle/wave [72].

In short, Nature disregards the clumsy attempts of humans to know it by imposing a priori

established criteria, mental categories and rules, and constraining it within the narrow limits

of the adopted perspective in the illusion of an “objective” knowledge. This inclination has an

analogy with the physiology of sight, which is based on a narrow clear vision (some 1-2% of the

visual field) surrounded by a blurred field; even if a clear, whole visual field would be available,

nothing existing outside it could be seen. As a result, seeing − with both sight and mind − closely

depends on a limited field of view: thus, it means being blind at the same time. Metaphorically,

it recalls the blindsight due to cortical blindness, where patients are able to respond to some

visual stimuli they cannot see and are not conscious of. In fact, in both everyday life and science,

we adapt to reality only perceiving a small part of it and neglecting what is not perceivable or

seemingly implausible, but with the duty to grasp it in order to improve knowledge, making

visible the invisible.

The way out from Western thought shortcomings calls for a shift of paradigm akin to the one

faced by quantum physics at the beginning of the 20th Century; such a need is witnessed by the

spread of quantum revolution to several disciplines other than physics in recent years,

including biology and the science of consciousness, where both quantum mechanisms and

quantum-like properties may be involved [73].

THE IMPLICATIONS OF QUANTUM PHYSICS AND ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY

The role of the observer has been reintroduced by quantum physicists, the only scientists who

felt the need to study consciousness in the early 20th century and move towards a unified

worldview. The interest of quantum physicists for consciousness is still ongoing, and several

intriguing hypotheses of its quantum implications have been introduced. They include three

main fields of interest:

Page 10 of 20

423

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

a) Quantum mechanisms in neurons [74–76]- a topic pertaining to the nascent quantum

biology [77–81]- as well as the observation of ultrafast hydrogen bond strengthening

between neighboring water molecules [82].

b) Epistemological implications of quantum physics, leading to the concept of quantum- like being introduced [73]- e.g., the quantum interpretation of mind processes like

decision making [83].

c) Hypotheses of a unified psychophysical world or a mental universe [84–89].

In short, the quantum implications of consciousness are both physically plausible and

epistemologically sound, despite ostensibly incompatible with classical thought; therefore, they

cannot be a priori rejected. On the contrary, they show the need for overcoming the above- mentioned shortcomings and constraints of Western classical thought, as emphasized by

Appleby:

“To construct an adequate non-Cartesian philosophy would take an enormous

amount of work. However, I believe there is reason to think that if we were to

undertake that project, it would lead to a conceptual revolution equal in magnitude

to the 17th century Cartesian one. In particular, it would lead to conceptions of the

world, and of human nature, which differed as much from the Cartesian conceptions

as the latter did from medieval conceptions” [90].

What Appleby holds from the perspective of modern physics perfectly fits with the above

discussion on the science of consciousness. The entirely new way of reasoning and processing

data brought by quantum physics is at the same time very old. In fact, the paradigm of both pre- Socratic and Eastern philosophies is more compatible with it than Western classical thought,

suggesting the need for seriously reappraising them by a transcultural, metaphilosophical

approach. In this regard, it is worth mentioning that the non-dualist approach of Eastern

philosophies allowed for a sound knowledge of the inner world, allowing to recognize the

unconscious and reach high levels of metacognition, resilience, and development of the Self

over 2,000 years ago with results not yet achieved by the Western thought [12,91].

The ancient philosophers-physicists, especially Heraclitus and Parmenides, held the

complementarity of the opposite (a principle reintroduced by physicist Wolfgang Pauli) and

their dynamic coevolution as a manifestation (appearance) of being. Not surprisingly, this is

akin to Taoism with its Yin/Yang polarity. In other words, there is a fil rouge − an

epistemological symmetry − linking the pre-Socratic and Eastern philosophies to quantum

physics; for example, the principle of reciprocal transformation of energy (Yang) and matter

(Yin) had been conceptually well established by Taoism over two millennia ago [73].

The model-dependent realism, recently introduced in physics [92], helps exceeding the

stalemate in the dispute between materialist monists and dualists by encompassing and

merging the physical and the mental worlds in a whole. It establishes that no concept of reality

independent from descriptions and theories may exist; therefore, science may only provide

effective partial models of it able to make correct predictions. The model-dependent realism is

in line with the Neurophenomenological Theory of the Three Worlds (NTTW) − an updated

version of Popper & Eccles’ theory (1977) − and may be considered as a further step towards

Page 11 of 20

424

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

the integration of inner and outer worlds in a whole. It establishes the inseparable

interrelationship between the physical world (World 1) and its mental representation (World

3) allowed by sense organs, brain circuitry, and coding processes (World 2). World 2 behaves

like a recording equipment processing available information (anyway partial) coming from the

outer world. Accordingly, one can draw the following conclusions: a) the nature of the world as

we know is Weltbild; b) the reality is an inseparable co-creation of both World 1 and 3; c)

arguably, there are as many Worlds 3 as sentient beings, depending on the features of their

World 2 − a fact provocatively well pictured by Thomas Nagel’s paper entitled What It Is Like to

Be a Bat? [94].

To summarize, the scientific revolution started by 20th Century physics strongly suggests the

need for a shift of paradigm (or better, its enlargement); one should also wonder whether a

metaphilosophical and metascientific approach exceeding the limits of the Western

ethnocentric perspective may allow for a deeper comprehension of consciousness.

TOWARDS A METAPHILOSOPHICAL AND METASCIENTIFIC APPROACH.

As mentioned above, the appearance of consciousness in the world, as well as its

development, probably started tens of thousands of years ago with an event named the

Sapient Paradox by Darwinian anthropologists, given that human DNA has been much the

same since about 100,000 years ago. Given that the diachronicity of consciousness and its

development is independent of DNA changes, it cannot be properly understood by an

inflexible materialist-reductionist standpoint neglecting the role of mind, experience, and

culture. Rather, it calls for a more comprehensive transdisciplinary approach, in order to

encompass the mind-brain-body-outer world dynamic relationships embedded in the

space-time dimension. If this is the case, the worldwide transcultural and transtemporal

presence of consciousness might be better faced by a metaphilosophical and metascientific

approach. It is worth emphasizing that metascientific does not mean non-scientific; indeed,

it pertains to a rigorous scientific way aimed to overcome the intrinsic limits of any single

discipline.

Generally speaking, it is reasonable to assume that limited ethnocentric perspectives are

no longer tenable in a globalized world, a relevant fact also in foreign policy [95]. Actually,

cultural differences should not be conceived anymore as sources of discrimination but be

appraised as sources of cultural enlargement, widening one’s perspective and allowing for

a better understanding between peoples [96]. In this regard, the “objectivity” yielded by an

inflexible ethnocentric and chronocentric stance, such as the positivist one, is weak at best

and doomed to failure.

Metaphilosophy can be defined as the philosophy of philosophy − viz., the investigation of

the nature of philosophy [97], dealing with the nature and possibility of knowledge and

understanding [98]. The metaphilosophical perspective − previously adopted in the

definition of the Self [12] − aims to recognize key concepts and meanings common to

different philosophies beyond their formal diversities and distinct modes of theorization.

The common field of reflection is aimed to find the problem’s unity in the multiplicity of

forms − i.e., to seek for connections rather than differences − and calls for getting out of

Page 12 of 20

425

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

one’s comfort zone, enter a heterotopic common field of reflection to properly understand

other cultures from inside and make them a food for self-transformation [99–101].

The concept of metaphilosophy is in line with that of metascience, an interdisciplinary

approach belonging to the most rigorous scientific stance with the aim to overcome the intrinsic

limits of single axiomatic disciplines. In fact, the Theorems of Incompleteness introduced by

Gödel in the 1930’ have shown the limitations of provability in formal axiomatic systems (see

[102] as a review). They have demonstrated that any consistent formal mathematical system,

a), necessarily includes undecidable, unprovable statements and, b), cannot prove from the

inside that it is consistent. Therefore, theories are intrinsically incomplete, despite including a

set of axioms and the proof relation of the given formalized system to make them decidable.

Gödel’s theorems deal with formal logic systems and mathematics, while their extensions to

other disciplines are more controversial; nevertheless, they set some constraints in empirical

sciences too, showing that they cannot provide demonstrations entailing mathematical

certainty [103].

Given the above limits, knowledge may be improved non-mathematically by enlarging the

theory with sound non-mathematical principles and/or moving towards an interdisciplinary

integration. An interesting example of the inclusion of the trans-scientific principles in science

is the anthropic principle in astrophysics, establishing that the values of physical and

cosmological quantities are not equally probable, but their range is restricted to those

compatible with the appearance of carbon-based life at some stage in its history [104–107]. All

versions of the anthropic principle include empirical trans-scientific assertions supporting a

theory and helping a connection between the “antecedent” and the “subsequent” [106], e.g., the

physical conditions and the biologic constraints, respectively. In other words, the anthropic

principle engenders a meta-level in order to exceed the limits of the discipline it refers to and,

therefore, it may be considered as an epistemological consequence of Gödel’s theorems.

As mentioned above, the application of Gödel’s theorems to disciplines other than mathematics,

such as neurosciences, remains a matter of debate. Still, it clearly lessens the Galilean

“mathematical certainty” and questions the self-sufficiency of any axiomatic discipline. Given

that the new sciences were born to study only physical phenomena with a mathematical

approach, it can be deduced that their paradigm cannot investigate consciousness and the

mind-brain-body relationship properly. Hence, a metaphilosophical and metascientific

approach integrating different disciplines may help improving their study since the 1PP, 2PP,

and the meaning of the experience in their variable cultural and chronological context are the

conditio sine qua non for their proper understanding.

CONCLUSIONS

The study of consciousness is a huge problem endowed with profound epistemological and

metaphysical implications. Even more, one can consider consciousness as the mother of all

problems, since the whole world (as we know it) is a product of consciousness and mind,

depending on what consciousness is and its ceaseless bidirectional relationship with the

physical reality.

The Galilean sciences resulted from the Western century-old rationalism, the Galileo and

Descartes’ mathematical-geometrical apriorism, and the compromise with the Church. As a

Page 13 of 20

426

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

whole, they behaved as powerful a cultural filter preventing the study of the soul

(consciousness) in medicine and leading to the observer being split by the observed fact in

physics until the 20th Century, in the illusion of its independence and neutrality. Thus, science

development was embedded in a prevailing egocentric, anthropocentric, and dualist stance −

the Descartes’ cogito ergo sum and the biblical idea of man’s dominion over nature − driven by

the will of power and calculative thinking [46,108]. According to Heidegger, calculative thinking

is aimed to dominate and manipulate the world, a purpose well defined by Descartes’

statement:

“...Et ainsi nous rendre comme maîtres et possesseurs de la nature” (Descartes,

1637, 6th part, p. 168).

In doing so, the calculative thinking splits the subject and the object, where the value of the

latter, living beings included, only depends on its utility and exploitation. Instead, the

meditative thinking is focused on meaning, which reigns in everything that is; despite not

utilitarian, meditative thinking is no less relevant than calculative one in the comprehension of

the world.

Science underwent a contentious divorce from the Church in the 17th Century; then, a

separation of science from philosophy occurred in the 18th Century, while in the early 20th

Century, physicalism claimed that science should get rid of any remnant of metaphysics (a self- contradictory metaphysical statement in itself). According to Husserl, modern scientific

disciplines can be considered as technical-professional derivation of that unique philosophy

meant as the rational investigation of the world, while any axiomatic discipline remains

inescapably based on metaphysical assumptions and incomplete. In his phenomenological

approach, he questioned the materialist-objectivist stance of positive sciences as a

transcendental naïvety [110], a fact calling for critically reappraising the mental processes

involved in the knowledge of the phenomenal world − i.e., how it appears in its givenness and

how one codifies it. Accordingly, the inseparable mind-brain-world relationship may be

approached starting from Heidegger’s Dasein (“being there” or “presence”) as the primary,

immediately given, condition of the existence in the world from which one cannot give up,

making consciousness and experience non-eliminable − i.e., “no consciousness, no world”, at

least as one can know it. This looks much simpler and tangible than a rationalist, abstract

conceptualization a priori splitting mind and matter, and discarding the former on the base of

a purported logical incompatibility, a fact recalling what Edgar Morin in his theory of

complexity defined as nothing crazier than the delusion of abstract coherence [111].

The separation of science from philosophy has been an unavoidable event, depending on the

increasing amount of information and the need to develop different languages to understand

the explored phenomena. On the other hand, this has resulted in an ever-increasing separation

of knowledge in a plenty of disciplines, specializations, and subspecializations, making

interdisciplinary communication hard, if possible. As a result, many scientists are inclined to

remain firmly anchored in their comfort zone, missing a comprehensive view of the whole, a

fact resembling a sort of dissociative process. Metaphorically, it has been well painted in the

Bible by the mythos of the Babel Tower, with its progressive growth and complexity resulting

Page 14 of 20

427

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

into the confusion of languages, the need to abandon it and start building up a new, hopefully,

better one.

Despite the fact that metaphysical speculations seem an ostensibly alien topic from the

perspective of hard sciences, they are entailed in the design of the paradigm at their basis.

Indeed, they were involved in the foundation and development of quantum physics in the early

20th Century to face the apparent absurdity of particles’ behavior. It is no accident that in this

process, quantum physicists seriously faced consciousness as well as pre-Socratic and Eastern

philosophies to implement the needed shift of paradigm with respect to classic Western

thought. Not surprisingly, the latter has been defined as the thought of the sunset of the West

by Heidegger and Severino [46,108], while the pre-Socratic thought, able to contemplate the

being and the nature as a whole, has been considered as the thought of the dawn, hopefully

leading to a new sunrise if properly implemented, a fact needing a new language and paradigm.

Indeed, physics − the most “materialist” and determinist of sciences − has outdone itself,

dismantling the linchpins of the classic thought, encompassing a probabilistic logic and the

complementarity of opposites; this has led to the observer and the observed phenomena being

rejoined in a whole and the place of consciousness in the world being reappraised, up to the

hypothesis of a mental universe [88].

If the above discussion is correct, medicine and life science should start walking in the route

opened by quantum physics and overcome the narrow limits of the conventional mechanist- reductionist approach with its conceptual fragmentation. Of course, the reductionist approach

to consciousness, aiming to solve the easy problem, remains of paramount importance for its

understanding and the capacity to manipulate its disorders. Its results may also help improving

self-knowledge and, thus, help philosophy overcome naïve views of mental faculties (e.g., free

will, cognition, and decision-making) in order to better understand how we are, judge, and

behave. Thus, neuropsychology can help philosophy by a better understanding of the

physiological aspects of higher-order processes and the inner-outer world relationship. On the

other hand, other disciplines such as philosophy, anthropology, and human sciences may

integrate and help neurosciences to better understand consciousness and the mind-brain- body-world relationship by contributing with non-mathematical valuable principles and sound

knowledge of humankind. For instance, it is worth mentioning the systematic exploration of the

inner world and inner-outer world relationship by Eastern philosophies, especially Taoism,

Yoga, and Buddhism, that have provided sound, epistemologically well-founded information on

their nature, also inspiring quantum physics [73]; therefore, they can no longer be evaded by

adopting a narrow ethnocentric and chronocentric stance.

References

[1] Jaynes J. La natura diacronica della coscienza. MIlano: Adelphi; 2014.

[2] Jaynes J. The origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the bicameral mind. Boston: Houghton Mifflin;

1990.

[3] Facco E, Lucangeli D, Tressoldi P. On the Science of Consciousness: Epistemological Reflections and

Clinical Implications. Explor J Sci Heal 2017; 13:163–80. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.explore.2017.02.007.

[4] Pockett S. Problems with theories that equate consciousness with information or information processing.

Front Syst Neurosci 2014;8 (art. 22:1–3. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnsys.2014.00225.

Page 15 of 20

428

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

[5] Chalmers DJ. How can we construct a science of consciousness? AnnNYAcadSci 2013; 1303:25–35.

[6] Chalmers DJ. The conscious mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 1996.

[7] Berganza CE, Mezzich JE, Pouncey C. Concepts of disease: their relevance for psychiatric diagnosis and

classification. Psychopathology 2005; 38:166–70.

[8] Wakefield JC. Misdiagnosing normality: Psychiatry’s failure to address the problem of false positive

diagnoses of mental disorder in a changing professional environment. J MentHealth 2010; 19:337–51.

[9] Frances A. The new crisis in psychiatry. Ann Intern Med 2013. https://doi.org/10.7326/0003-4819-159-

3-201308060-00655.

[10] Facco E, Fracas F, Tressoldi P. Moving beyond the concept of altered state of consciousness: the Non- Ordinary Mental Expressions (NOMEs). Adv Soc Sci Res J 2021; 8:615–31.

https://doi.org/10.14738/ASSRJ.83.9935.

[11] James W. The Varieties of Religious Experience. A Study in Human Nature. Kindle Edi. New York, NY, USA:

Longmans, Green, & Co; 1917.

[12] Facco E, Al Khafaji BE, Tressoldi P. In search of the true self. J Theor Philos Psychol 2019; 39:157–80.

[13] Tye M. Qualia. In: Zalta EN, editor. Stanford Encycl. Philos., Stanford, CA, USA: 2018, p. 1–39.

[14] Sturm T. Consciousness regained? Philosophical arguments for and against reductive physicalism.

DialoguesClinNeurosci 2012; 14:55–63.

[15] Jackson F. Epiphenomenal Qualia. Philos Q 1982; 32:127–36. https://doi.org/10.2307/2960077.

[16] Kirk R. Zombies. In: Zalta EN, editor. Stanford Encycl. Philos., Stanford, CA, USA: Stanford Encyclopedia of

philosophy; 2019, p. 1–32.

[17] Solms M, Panksepp J. The “Id” Knows More than the “Ego” Admits: Neuropsychoanalytic and Primal

Consciousness Perspectives on the Interface Between Affective and Cognitive Neuroscience. Brain Sci

2012; 2:147–75. https://doi.org/10.3390/brainsci2020147.

[18] Facco E. Pain, the uknown: epistemological issues and related clinical implications. Minerva Anestesiol

2021. https://doi.org/10.23736/S0375-9393.21.15920-6.

[19] Levine J. Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap. Pacific Philos Q 1983; 64:354–61.

[20] Marras A. Consciousness and reduction. Br J Philos Sci 2005; 56:335–61.

[21] Morris K. Does Functional Reduction Need Bridge Laws? A Response to Marras. Br J Philos Sci 2009;

60:647–57.

[22] IASP. Pain terms: a list with definitions and notes on usage. Recommended by the IASP Subcommittee on

Taxonomy. Pain 1979; 6:249–52.

[23] Raja SN, Carr DB, Cohen M, Finnerup NB, Flor H, Gibson S, et al. The revised International Association for

the Study of Pain definition of pain: concepts, challenges, and compromises. Pain 2020; 161:1976–82.

https://doi.org/10.1097/j.pain.0000000000001939.

[24] Facco E, Bacci C, Zanette G. Hypnosis as sole anesthesia for oral surgery: The egg of Columbus. J Am Dent

Assoc 2021; 152:756–62. https://doi.org/10.1016/J.ADAJ.2021.04.017.

Page 16 of 20

429

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

[25] Thompson T, Terhune DB, Oram C, Sharangparni J, Rouf R, Solmi M, et al. The effectiveness of hypnosis for

pain relief: A systematic review and meta-analysis of 85 controlled experimental trials. Neurosci Biobehav

Rev 2019; 99:298–310. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.02.013.

[26] Casiglia E, Finatti F, Tikhonoff V, Stabile MR, Mitolo M, Albertini F, et al. Mechanisms of hypnotic analgesia

explained by functional magnetic resonance (fMRI). Int J Clin Exp Hypn 2020; 68:1–15.

https://doi.org/10.1080/00207144.2020.1685331.

[27] Fumerton R. Speckled Hens and Objects of Acquaintance. Philos Perspect 2005; 19:121–38.

[28] Le Breton D. Esperienze del dolore. Tra distruzione e rinascita. Torino: Raffaello Cortina Editore; 2010.

[29] Le Breton D. Antropologia del dolore. Sesto San Giovanni, MI: Meltemi; 2007.

[30] Feinberg TE, Mallatt JM. Subjectivity “demystified”: Neurobiology, evolution, and the explanatory gap.

Front Psychol 2019;10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01686.

[31] Irvine E. Old Problems with New Measures in the Science of Consciousness. Br J Philos Sci 2012; 63:627–

48. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axs019.

[32] Irvine E. Consciousness as a Scientific Concept: A Philosophy of Science Perspective. Dordrecht, The

Netherlands.: Springer; 2012.

[33] Burtt EA. The Metaphysical Foundation of Modern Science. Mineaola, NY, US: Dover Publications; 2003.

[34] Facco E. A neurophenomenological theory of the three worlds. Theory Psychol 2022; 32:733–53.

https://doi.org/10.1177/09593543211068426.

[35] Facco E, Tagliagambe S. Learning from the past: from incubation in ancient Egypt and Greece to modern

hypnosis. Adv Soc Sci Res J 2021; 8:268–85. https://doi.org/10.14738/assrj.87.10541.

[36] Kuziemsky C. Decision-making in healthcare as a complex adaptive system. Healthc Manag Forum

2016;29:4–7. https://doi.org/10.1177/0840470415614842.

[37] Ma’ayan A. Complex systems biology. J R Soc Interface 2017; 14:20170391.

https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2017.0391.

[38] Schirber M. Nobel Prize: Complexity, from Atoms to Atmospheres. Physics (College Park Md) 2021; 14:1–

3. https://doi.org/10.1103/PHYSICS.14.141.

[39] Parisi G. Order parameter for spin-glasses. Phys Rev Lett 1983; 50:1946–8.

https://doi.org/10.1103/PHYSREVLETT.50.1946.

[40] Parisi G. Infinite number of order parameters for spin-glasses. Phys Rev Lett 1979; 43:1754–6.

https://doi.org/10.1103/PHYSREVLETT.43.1754.

[41] Ballerini M, Cabibbo N, Candelier R, Cavagna A, Cisbani E, Giardina I, et al. Empirical investigation of

starling flocks: a benchmark study in collective animal behaviour. Anim Behav 2008; 76:201–15.

https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1016/j.anbehav.2008.02.004.

[42] Parisi G. Complexity in Biology: The Point of View of a Physicist. ArXiv:Cond-Mat/ 1994;9412018v1:1–5.

[43] Facco E, Agrillo C, Greyson B. Epistemological implications of near-death experiences and other non- ordinary mental expressions: Moving beyond the concept of altered state of consciousness. Med

Hypotheses 2015; 85:85–93. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.mehy.2015.04.004.

Page 17 of 20

430

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

[44] Damasio A. Descartes’ error. New York: G.P. Putnam; 1994.

[45] Ryle G. The concept of mind. London, UK: Hutchinson; 1949.

[46] Severino E. The Essence of Nihilism. Brooklin, NY, USA: Verso; 2016.

[47] Galilei G. Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche intorno a due nuove scienze. UK: CreateSpace

Independent Publishing Platform, 2015; 1638.

[48] Florenskij P. The Pillar and Ground of the Truth: An Essay in Orthodox Theodicy in Twelve Letters.

Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press; 2004.

[49] La Mettrie OJ. Machine Man and Other Writings. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996; 1747.

[50] Facco E, Tagliagambe S. Ritornare a Ippocrate. Riflessioni sulla medicina di oggi. Milano, Italy: Mondadori

Università; 2020.

[51] Facco E, Casiglia E, Zanette G, Testoni I. On the way of liberation from suffering and pain: role of hypnosis

in palliative care. Ann Palliat Med 2017:1–12.

[52] Gould SJ. Nonoverlapping magisteria. Nat Hist 1997; 16:16–22.

[53] Alberts B. Preface. Sci. Creat. A view from Natl. Acad. Sci. 2nd ed., Washington, USA: National Academic

Press; 1999, p. viii–ix.

[54] Wulff M. D. Mystical Experiences. In: Cardena E, Lynn J. S, Krippner S, editors. Var. anomalous Exp.

Examining Sci. evidence, Washington, USA: American Psychological Association.; 2014.

[55] Greyson B. Congruence Between Near-Death and Mystical Experience. Int J Psychol Relig 2014; 24:298–

310. https://doi.org/10.1080/10508619.2013.845005.

[56] Lifshitz M, van Elk M, Luhrmann TM. Absorption and spiritual experience: A review of evidence and

potential mechanisms. Conscious Cogn 2019;73. https://doi.org/10.1016/J.CONCOG.2019.05.008.

[57] Forman RCK. What does mysticism have to teach us about consciousness? JConsciousness Stud 1998;

5:185–201.

[58] Derbyshire SW, Whalley MG, Stenger VA, Oakley DA. Cerebral activation during hypnotically induced and

imagined pain. Neuroimage 2004; 23:392–401. https://doi.org/doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2004.04.033.

[59] Rainville P, Hofbauer RK, Bushnell MC, Duncan GH, Price DD. Hypnosis modulates activity in brain

structures involved in the regulation of consciousness. JCogn Neurosci 2002; 14:887–901.

[60] Russell B. Problems of Philosophy. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 1912.

[61] van Riel R, Van Gulick R. Scientific Reduction. Stanford Encycl. Philos., Stanford, CA, USA: Stanford

Encyclopedia of philosophy; 2019, p. 1–78.

[62] Popper KR. Objective Knoweldge. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 1972.

[63] Nagel E. The Structure of Science. Problems in the Logic of Explanation. New York, NY, USA: Harcourt,

Brace & World; 1961.

[64] Charles A. The pathophysiology of migraine: implications for clinical management. Lancet Neurol 2018;

17:174–82. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1474-4422(17)30435-0.

Page 18 of 20

431

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

[65] Flynn N. Systematic Review of the Effectiveness of Hypnosis for the Management of Headache. Int J Clin

Exp Hypn 2018; 66:343–52. https://doi.org/10.1080/00207144.2018.1494432.

[66] Linde K, Allais G, Brinkhaus B, Manheimer E, Vickers A, White AR. Acupuncture for migraine prophylaxis.

In: Linde K, editor. Cochrane Database Syst. Rev., Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd; 2009.

https://doi.org/10.1002/14651858.CD001218.pub2.

[67] Forbes RB, McCarron M, Cardwell CR. Efficacy and Contextual (Placebo) Effects of CGRP Antibodies for

Migraine: Systematic Review and Meta-analysis. Headache 2020; 60:1542–57.

https://doi.org/10.1111/head.13907.

[68] Bedau MA. Weak Emergence. In: Tomberlin J, editor. Philos. Perspect. Mind, Causation, World., Malden,

MA, USA: Blackwell Publishing Inc; 1997, p. 375–99.

[69] Cohen AA. Complex systems dynamics in aging: new evidence, continuing questions. Biogerontology 2016;

17:205–20. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10522-015-9584-x.

[70] Eeles E, Teodorczuk A, Mitleton-Kelly E. Reconceptualizing delirium as a disorder of complex system

failure. Med Hypotheses 2018; 118:121–6. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.mehy.2018.06.031.

[71] Howsepian AA. Reductionism Revised: Return of the Biomedical Model. In: Leigh H, editor. Biopsychosoc.

Approaches Prim. Care State Art Challenges 21st Century., New York, NY, USA: Springer Science + Business

Media; 1997, p. 179–200.

[72] Merli PG, Missiroli GF, Pozzi G. Electron interferometry with the Elmiskop 101 electron microscope. J Phys

E 1974; 7:729–32. https://doi.org/10.1088/0022-3735/7/9/016.

[73] Facco E, Fracas F. De Rerum (Incerta) Natura: A Tentative Approach to the Concept of “Quantum- like” Symmetry (Basel) 2022;14:1–13. https://doi.org/10.3390/sym14030480.

[74] Penrose R. The Emperor’s New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics. Oxford, UK:

Oxford University Press; 2016.

[75] Poznanski RR, Tuszynski JA, Feinberg TE. Biophysics of Consciousness. London, UK: World Scientific

Publishing Co. Pte Ltd; 2017.

[76] Beck F, Eccles JC. Quantum aspects of brain activity and the role of consciousness. Proc Natl Academy Sci

USA 1992; 89:11357–61. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.89.23.11357.

[77] Lambert N, Chen YN, Cheng YC, Li CM, Chen GY, Nori F. Quantum biology. Nat Phys 2013; 9:18.

[78] Bordonaro M, Ogryzko V. Quantum biology at the cellular level--elements of the research program.

Biosystems 2013; 112:11–30.

[79] Melkikh A V, Khrennikov A. Nontrivial quantum and quantum-like effects in biosystems: Unsolved

questions and paradoxes. ProgBiophysMolBiol 2015; 119:137–61.

[80] Gould JL. Animal Navigation: Birds Have Magnetic Maps. CurrBiol 2015;25: R836–8.

[81] Heyers D, Elbers D, Bulte M, Bairlein F, Mouritsen H. The magnetic map sense and its use in fine-tuning the

migration programme of birds. J Comp Physiol A NeuroetholSensNeural Behav Physiol 2017.

[82] Yang J, Dettori R, Nunes JPF, List NH, Biasin E, Centurion M, et al. Direct observation of ultrafast hydrogen

bond strengthening in liquid water. Nat 2021 5967873 2021; 596:531–5.

https://doi.org/10.1038/s41586-021-03793-9.

Page 19 of 20

432

Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal (ASSRJ) Vol. 10, Issue 1, January-2023

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

[83] Wang Z, Solloway T, Shiffrin RM, Busemeyer JR. Context effects produced by question orders reveal

quantum nature of human judgments. ProcNatlAcadSciUSA 2014; 111:9431–6.

[84] Atmanspacher H. At home in the quantum world. Behav Brain Sci 2013; 36:276–7.

[85] Barlow PW. The natural history of consciousness, and the question of whether plants are conscious, in

relation to the Hameroff-Penrose quantum-physical “Orch OR” theory of universal consciousness.

CommunIntegrBiol 2015;8: e1041696.

[86] Neppe VM, Close ER. The concept of relative non-locality: theoretical implications in consciousness

research. Explore (NY) 2015; 11:102–8.

[87] Walach H, Romer H. Generalized entanglement - A nonreductive option for a phenomenologically dualist

and ontologically monist view of consciousness. In: Walach H, Schmidt S, Wayne BJ, editors. Neurosci.

Conscious. Spirituality., Dordrecht: Springer; 2011, p. 81–96.

[88] Henry RC. The mental Universe. Nature 2005; 436:29.

[89] D’Ariano MG, Faggin F. Hard Problem and Free Will: an information-theoretical approach. In: Scardigli F,

editor. Artif. Intell. Nat. Conscious., New York, NY, USA: Srpinger; 2022, p. in press.

https://doi.org/10.48550/arxiv.2012.06580.

[90] Appleby DM. Mind and Matter. Cornell Univeristy Libr - Hystory Philos Phys 2013:1–26.

[91] Facco E. Hypnosis and resilience: a metaphilosophic perspective. Int J Psyco-Anthropology 2021; 1:1–19.

[92] Hawking S, Mlodinow L. The Grand Design. New York, NY, USA: Bantam Books; 2010.

[93] Popper KR, Eccles JC. The Self and His Brain. Berlin, Germany: Springer-Verlag; 1977.

[94] Nagel T. Philosophical Review What Is It Like to Be a Bat? Source Philos Rev 1974; 83:435–50.

[95] Facco E, Tagliagambe S. The Century-Old Swinging of Russia Between Order and Dissolution, East and

West: A Historical and Psychocultural Insight in the Russian-Ukrainian War. Adv Soc Sci Res J 2022;

9:447–60. https://doi.org/10.14738/ASSRJ.911.13497.

[96] Jullien F. Il n’y a pas d’Identité Culturelle mai Nous Défendons les Resources d’une Culture. Paris, France:

Éditions de L’Herne; 2016.

[97] Lazerowitz M. A note on metaphylosophy. Metaphilosophy 1970; 1:91.

[98] Overgaard S, Gilbert P, Burwood S. Introduction: what good is metaphilosophy? An Introd. to

Metaphilosophy., Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 2013, p. 1–10.

https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139018043.

[99] Burik S. Opening philosophy to the world: derrida and education in philosophy. Educ Theory 2009;

59:297–312. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1741-5446.2009.00320.x.

[100] Weber R. “How to Compare?” – On the Methodological State of Comparative Philosophy. Philos Compass

2013; 8:593–603.

[101] Jullien F. De l’Etre au Vivre. Lexique eurochinoise de la pensée. Paris, France: Gallimard; 2015.

[102] Raatikainen P. Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems. In: Zalta EN, editor. Stanford Encycl. Philos., Stanford,

CA, USA: University of Stanford, CA, US; 2018, p. 1–68.

Page 20 of 20

433

Facco, E., Fracas, F., & Tagliagambe, S. (2023). Consciousness and the Mind-Brain-Body-World Relationship: Towards A Transdisciplinary and

Transcultural Approach. Advances in Social Sciences Research Journal, Vol - 10(1). 414-433.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/assrj.101.13896

[103] Buechner J. Are the Godel incompleteness theorems limitative results for the neurosciences? J BiolPhys

2010; 36:23–44.

[104] Carter B. Large Number Coincidences and the Anthropic Principle in Cosmology. In: Longair MS, editor.

Confront. Cosmol. Theor. with Obs. Data., Dordrecht, The Netherlands.: Reidel; 1974, p. 291–8.

[105] Carter B. Republication of: large number coincidences and the anthropic principle in cosmology. Gen

Relativ Gravit 2011; 43:3225–33. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10714-011-1258-7.

[106] Rebaglia A. Critica della ragione metascientifica. Milano: Franco Angeli; 1996.

[107] Barrow JD, Tipler FJ. The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 1988.

[108] Heidegger M. Being and Time. New York, NY, USA: Harper Perennil Modern Classics; 2008.

[109] Descartes R. Discours de la méthode. Paris, France: Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, Éd. Gallimard, 1966; 1637.

[110] Husserl E. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to

Phenomenological Philosophy. Evanstone: Northwestern University Press; 1970.

[111] Morin E. La sfida della complessità. La défi de la complexité. Milano, Italy: GaiaMente, Le lettere; 2011.