Page 1 of 18

European Journal of Applied Sciences – Vol. 12, No. 3

Publication Date: June 25, 2024

DOI:10.14738/aivp.123.16966

Englman, R., & Yahalom, A. (2024). A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness; Memory Experiments. European Journal of

Applied Sciences, Vol - 12(3). 29-46.

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom

A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness

Memory Experiments

R. Englman

Ariel University, Ariel 40700, Israel

A. Yahalom

Ariel University, Ariel 40700, Israel

ABSTRACT

Inspired by works of W. H. Zurek and others, a mathematical, physical theory,

entirely within a quantum mechanical formalism, is proposed for cognitive

processes in terms of an abstract Hilbert-space for the conscious state that is an

exact replica of the Hilbert-space for the neuronic physical state. Thus, any actual

state of consciousness arises by its formal alignment (identification) with some-one

in the set of the neuronic states, with the latter undergoing perpetual changes in the

wake of life-long experiences. It is posited that these changes become expressed by

an increase in the number of ordered, coherent neuronic states at the expense of

the preordinal random neuronic states. Changes, transitions between states are

induced by a Gorini-Kossakowski-Sudarshan-Lindblad formalism, which is also

instrumental in the effect of the conscious state on bodily actions. The paradigmatic

findings of R.N. Shepard (1958 - 2011) and of S. Sternberg (1966 - 2016) for long- and short-term recalls are interpreted within the model.

Keywords: Quantum Mechanics, mental states, awareness, mind-body interaction, sense- impressions, memory.

INTRODUCTION

[Definition: Briefly, Hilbert space is an ordered collective in quantum mechanics (q.m.) of all

possible states of a given system.]

Consciousness was defined in NEB (1980), quoting John Locke, as ”the perception of what

passes in one’s mind”, and similarly as ”the intuitive perception of experience and the flow of

inner time” by Atkinson (2011), or in a more nuanced form as ”sentience, awareness,

subjectivity, qualia, the ability to experience or to feel, wakefulness, having a sense of self-hood,

and the executive control system of the mind” (Farthing 1992). Regarding consciousness in

animals other than humans, the jury is still out, notwithstanding a weighty declaration that the

neural conditions in animals are also favorable for it (Low 2012).

Historically, Tononi and Edelman (1998) with their concept of a re-entrant functioning of the

mind (reminiscent of ”mean field” theories of phase transitions in physics), may be regarded as

the prime movers of a scientific, mathematical study of consciousness, an approach that has

further been continued more recently by e.g., Lamme (2006). With a growth of research

Page 2 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 30

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

activities in the field, both experimental and theoretical, more kinds of different theories of

consciousness have come to be recognized: e.g., nominally three in one version (Link 2022) and

over twenty in another survey (Seth and Bayne 2022). The theorizing concern with

consciousness spans several disciplines: philosophy, psychology, neurology, biology,

chemistry, information sciences and, more recently, physics. Distinct approaches include

higher order theories (HOT), by which consciousness emerges as the result of some higher

order mental activity (Rosenthal 2005). Then, one has global workspace theories (Baars 1988,

Dehaene and Nacache 2001), which associate with the conscious state the propensity to give it

an outward expression, e.g., by talking, deliberate acting, etc. Additionally, other views relate

consciousness to a unique combination of electro- and chemical processes, these taking is

placed exclusively in the brain (Levine 1983, Block 2009). A more exhaustive account of the

further, numerous theoretical approaches to interpret mental activities erstwhile in terms of

the neural framework is beyond the scope of this paper and so is the assignment of the different

types of mental events to their location in the brain or the specification of any brain component

[e.g., synapses, microtubules (Hameroff and Penrose 2014)] primarily involved in cognition.

Attributions of quantum aspects to mental activities, as in the present study, are not new and

are on the increase as of late, but it is here that a formal and inclusive formalism is offered anew.

In the past, looking backwards over several decades, one might recall a proposed interaction in

reverse between cognition and q.m. due to E. P. Wigner, who sought the solution for the infinite

regress problem of quantum mechanical observation in the mind of the observer (Wigner

1961). An association of intelligent decisions with quantum mechanics was proposed early by

Asano et al (2011), continued by Khrennikov (2019) and Khrennikov and Asano (2020).

Previous work on quantum mechanical aspects of cognitive processes was categorized by Hu

and Wu (2010). Notably, a formal identification between quantum mechanics and psychology

was made by Khrennikov (2019), where, in equation (20), the wave-mechanical function Ψ

made his appearance for the mental state. Quantum entanglement in bipartite systems and

violations of Bell-inequalities were pinpointed in psychological events by Aerts and

collaborators (2019). Noting some phenomenological aspects of decision making in human

affairs both by human individuals and collectives, the authors of a series of papers, in e.g.,

Pothos and Busemeyer (2013), Busemeyer and Bruza (2012), Wang et al (2013) showed that

these obeyed quantum mechanical rules of probabilities, rather than classical, Boolean or

Bayesian ones. Specifically, this conclusion was reached on the basis of empirical evidences

relating to non-commutativity (i.e., temporal order effects) in decision making,

complementarity (interference between different decision path-ways, such as in binocular

rivalry), super-positions (of alternative choices) and the bistable perception of ambiguous

events, all of which feature in processes of choice and decision. Other instances mentioned were

the so-called conjunctions fallacy, for whose resolution the authors in Pothos and Busemeyer

(2013) resort to an expression in terms of a quantum state function. The” Linda paradox” of

Kahanman and Tversky (1983), illustrating a falsely conceived dichotomy between her being a

feminist and a bank-teller, is further quoted there as pertaining to the quantum domain. A

related outcome of the identification with quantum mechanics is the derivation of a generalized

Jarzynski equality and a generalized Crooks’ theorem for decision-making (Braun-Moya,

Kru ̈ger and Braun 2018), in which the energy is replaced by the” utility function”.

Page 3 of 18

31

Englman, R., & Yahalom, A. (2024). A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness; Memory Experiments. European Journal of Applied Sciences,

Vol - 12(3). 29-46.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/aivp.123.16966

All these motivate the present authors to propose a formulation of mental activities in a fully

quantum setting, touching also, but not solving (or intending to solve), the mind-body problem.

What follows, then, is a quantum mechanical description of cognitive processes, with prospects

of future extensions and empirical predictions, not as yet provided.

FORMALISM

We formalize these findings, by postulating three disjoint Hilbert spaces, together with their

representatives (state functions) at any instant of time (t), consisting of a) the physical state of

the neurons [φf(n,t)], b) the actual mental state involved in any cognitive process [ψp(m,t)], c)

the physical state of the rest of the bodily organs, excluding the neurons [χk(b,t)]. Thus, the

state-function is written in a basis of a product:

Ψf,p,k(n,m,b,t) = φf(n,t)ψp(m,t)χk(b,t) ≡ Ψi (1)

with the vectorial sub-indexes f,p,k mapped onto the single vectorial index i and omission of

time, for brevity.

There being a multitude of neurons and of bodily organs, each with its own multitude of DOF,

the functions in a) and c) are representations of long product functions (assuming at this stage

independence between the DOF), with the possibility of entangled super-positions of product

functions taking, as bases, the following form:

φf(n,t) = φf1(q1)φf2(q2)...φfNneu(qNneu) (2)

for Nneu neural DOF (the q’s). Analogous products form the bases for the function χ in c),

involving the bodily organs numbering, say, Norg and it will turn out after our introduction of

the” alignment” later in this section that for the mental state functions represented in b) the

bases are in correspondence with (in fact, duals of) those in the equation 2 above.

The employment of a quantum mechanical formalism for the first and third factors in the above

need hardly to be commented on, insomuch as they relate to physical objects (essentially,

molecules although of an immensely large number and of a complicated kind). The following

quote by the noted cognitive psychologist, R.N. Shepard is in order:”Human beings and all other

animals are themselves physical systems and, as such, operate in compliance with physical

laws” (Shepard 2004). A more explicit quote stressing the physics background of neural

activities is due to Zurek (2014): ” ... the higher mental processes all correspond to well-defined

but, at present, poorly understood information processing functions that are carried out by

physical systems, our brains. Described in this manner, awareness becomes susceptible to

physical analysis. In particular, the process of decoherence is bound to affect the states of the

brain: Relevant observables of individual neurons, including chemical concentrations and

electrical potentials, are macroscopic. They obey classical, dissipative equations of motion.

Thus, any quantum superposition of the states of neurons will be destroyed far too quickly for

us to become conscious of quantum goings-on: Decoherence applies to our own” state of

mind”.”. This is followed there by an evolutionary hypothesis:

” One might still ask why the preferred basis of neurons becomes correlated with the classical

observables in the familiar universe. The selection of available interaction Hamiltonians is

Page 4 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 32

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

limited and must constrain the choices of the detectable observables. There is, however,

another process that must have played a decisive role: Our senses did not evolve for the

purpose of verifying quantum mechanics. Rather, they developed through a process in which

survival of the fittest played a central role. And when nothing can be gained from prediction,

there is no evolutionary reason for perception. Moreover, only classical states are robust in

spite of decoherence and therefore have predictable consequences. Hence one might argue that

we had to evolve to perceive classical reality.”.

[Though, not everyone shares this view. Thus T. Nagel (2012) writes:” The existence of

consciousness seems to imply that the physical description of the universe, in spite of its

richness and explanatory power, is only part of the truth, and that the natural order is far less

austere than it would be if physics and chemistry accounted for everything. If we take this

problem seriously, and follow out its implications, it threatens to unravel the entire naturalistic

world picture”.]

What needs to be stated clearly is that the first factor-function φ, representing the neuronic

state is the potential and actual repository of all human experiences. The Hilbert space for this

factor is of course of a prodigiously large dimensionality: thus, by supposing just two possible

states for every neuron (e.g., off and on, (Amit1989), section 6.5.1), the Hilbert space of the first

factor is 2 to-the-power of the number of neurons in the brain (estimated at 86 billion for

humans). Furthermore, it seems possible to posit as a guiding idea, that a ”virgin”, un- experienced brain is composed of collective neuronic states in which diverse neurons are

connected by the connectional architecture in the brain, possibly in an entangled form, but in

essentially random, disorganized arrangements, i.e., with no regular correlations between

individual neuron states in a collective state. An experience or external stimulus causes a

collective state to become organized, regular, orderly in a way that resembles a paramagnetic- to-ferromagnetic phase-transition. Further experiences do the same for additional collective

states, so that there is a one-to-one correspondence between the experiences and the number

of orderly collective states, all this happening without regard to the energy of the states or to

the prevailing temperature.

This model of cooperative transition is supported by researchers of an extensive observation

on 40 retinal ganglion cells of salamander (Schneidmanet et al. 2006), (further confirmed for

monkey eyes (Shlens et al. 2014)), who found that a model of weakly correlated neuronic units

is equivalent to the Ising model with pairwise coupling in Statistical Physics. Their conclusion

is reached after noting that the observed frequency of collective spiking is many orders of

magnitudes larger than that arising from a model of independent neurons. Clearly, such

coordinated spiking is a hallmark of a coherent collective neuronic state. Subsequent work in

Tkacik et al. (2014) on up to 200 retinal cells reinforced the model and led to the authors’

writing:” It is widely agreed that .... percepts, thoughts, and actions require the coordinated

activity of many neurons in a network, not the independent activity of many individual

neurons”. Neuronal ferromagnetic versus paramagnetic phases had been found (Rotondo et al.

2018), with the former favored by weak quantum effects and low temperatures.

The quoted dictum of R.N. Shepard (2004) holds equally well for the third factor-function χ,

that represents the bodily state after the mental process, such as uttering a sound (in speaking),

Page 5 of 18

33

Englman, R., & Yahalom, A. (2024). A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness; Memory Experiments. European Journal of Applied Sciences,

Vol - 12(3). 29-46.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/aivp.123.16966

moving a finger or taking a step. Admittedly these activities are more parsimoniously described

classically, e.g., by Mechanics of muscular action, nevertheless, for consistency we choose to

stay within a quantum formalism to formulate also bodily activities. In this formalism, the

dynamics is represented as transitions between quantum states, of which later. Alternatively, a

mental process may be followed not by a bodily change, but by a subsequent mental activity

(like thinking, contemplating) or an altered feeling (e.g., being afraid or elated); in this case

third factor stays constant and it is the middle state-factor that undergoes change(s). We now

turn to this item, which, in its form, is essentially the newcomer in the theory (although the

several cited works in the” Introduction” have paved the way to its inclusion into a fully

quantum formulation.)

The middle factor-function ψ is a vector in the Hilbert-space of all mental states. In the theory

this space is posited to be in a one-to-one correspondence with the actual, momentarily

prevailing neuronic Hilbert space (and therefore possesses the same dimensionality as that).

At any moment the mental state occupied (meaning, sensed by the person) is one that is the

reflection of one, single neuronic state. If this neuronic state is the creation of a past experience,

etc., that is to say ordered, the mental state will qualify as a conscious state; if, however the

mental state is aligned with a random, un-organized neuronic state, then the possessor of this

mental state will be lacking consciousness at that moment.

Putting in numbers, if one associates the conscious states with thoughts in the mind, one may

find an estimate for the maximal number of conscious states achievable in a human lifetime, as

108 - 109, based on 10k-100k thoughts per day. Now, this number is infinitesimally small

compared to the astronomically large number of neuronic states. In an alternative estimation,

if one may associate the collective coherent states with the meta-stable correlated states, the

number of the former grows exponentially with the number of neurons Nneu, roughly as 0.1 x

100.03Nneu, which again is much smaller than the number of neuronic states. [This is based on

Figure 10 in Tkacik et al (2014). An early estimate, due to von Neumann, based on the observed

spike frequency is about 1020 (Amit 1989), section 6.1.1.] How is it, then, that human beings are

thoughtful most of the day? The answer seems to lie in the evolutionary hypothesis of Zurek

(2014) quoted above.

The postulated neuron-consciousness correspondence has its analogue in the mapping,

erstwhile put forward by John Maynard-Smith, between genotypes (the stored biological

information) and phenotypes (functional or observed properties), allowing in that case for a

redundancy (many-to-one correspondence) quantified in Greenbury et al (2016) and recently

discussed critically in Sappington and Mohanty (2023). Our model of a single-mode alignment

is a null hypothesis, which may be modified without essentially altering the main concept.

The above process of alignment between the state of consciousness and a neuronic state, or

their duality, that is central to the theory, is just one of the transitions taking place and will be

treated in the next section under” Dynamics of Cognition”. Alignment between states in

different Hilbert spaces is not without parallel, in as much as it forms the critical step in von

Neumann’s quantum measurement theory, through the process of aligning the states of the

microscopic observable with the states of the pointer (E.g., equation (2.5) in Leggett (1980). As

is well known (e.g., Moreira-Almeida et al. 2018), there are two main approaches to the mind-

Page 6 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 34

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

body problem: Physicalism, according to which mind is a material or physical process, a

product of the functioning of the brain. In contrast, dualism claims that mind is something other

than, and could exist apart from, the brain. The here proposed alignment mechanism bridges

between the two approaches.

DYNAMICS OF COGNITION

Life means changes (activity) (Marx 1867). Irreversible changes in physical systems are

currently described by the Gorini-Kossakowski-Sudarshan-Lindblad (GKSL) formalism, which

is an extension of the time-dependent Schrödinger equation for the density matrix of systems

in interaction with their surroundings, such that the densities are non-negative and their trace

sums to unity at all times (Gorini et al 1976, Lindblad 1976). The density matrix arises as the

components of the density operator being a function of time.

ρ ≡ |Ψ >< Ψ| (3)

The range and conditions of validity of the GKSL-equation have been the subject of numerous

investigations, in which the equation is derived for a microscopic system coupled to a

macroscopic environment. In most of the treatments this coupling is postulated as weak, in the

sense of its lying below the energy spread of the system’s Hamiltonian. In the derivation of the

GKSL-equation in Pearle (2012), this requirement is not noted. But in Kosloff (2013) the weak

system-bath coupling limit is explicitly postulated, additionally to a thermalization time that is

slower than the inverse energy spread in the system. In this limit, the system-environment

interaction energy may be neglected. The uniqueness of the Lindblad formalism was studied in

Barra and Liedo (2018). In an extensive review by Rivas and Huelga (2018), one finds a sally in

their section 7.3 to the strong coupling, non-Markovian regime with a generator of the

Lindbladian form that preserves positivity.

We recall Lindblad’s equation for the time varying density of states operator ρ as being of the

following form:

(4)

in which the gammas are cofactors and Ln are the Lindblad operators for a set of n’s. We now

postulate having a single summand in the second term, conventionally named” Dissipator” D(ρ),

and rewrite this in the bra-ket form as:

(5)

Page 8 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 36

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

1. Perception, change in the neuronic state: neuronic state index in Eq 1changing from f to

f

0, with other indices invariant.

2. Consciousness, recognition of neuronic change: p (aligned to f) → p0 (aligned to f

0)

3. Bodily activity: k → k

0 → k” ....

4. Instinctive action: Process I → process III without intervention of process II.

5. Other unconscious activity, including dreaming and one satisfying a Turing test: Process

I → process III without intervention of process II.

AN ILLUSTRATION

We assume that the density of states ρ for the neuronic states Ψi in equation 1 may be written

at some initial time t = −∞ in a diagonal representation (and, similarly, for the analogous

functions of the consciousness). To mimic the effect of an experience starting at t = 0 on ρ, we

suppose that one of the factors, say the first, in Ψi represents a partially disordered neuronic

state, with the rest of the factors spanning any arbitrary number of ordered states, bearing the

imprint of previous sense impressions. Suppose now, further, that the new experience changes

this first factor into an ordered neuronic state. If the two, initial and final, neuronic states are

labelled respectively ρin and ρfin, this simply means that the occupation numbers (probabilities)

1 and 0 for ρin and for ρfin are interchanged due to the new experience. In the present theory this

transition is driven by a Lindblad operator.

In Figure 1 we illustrate the working of the Lindblad operator for a toy example involving only

a paltry of five neuronic states (instead of the myriad in a realistic situation). The occupation

probabilities of the neuronic states are shown by a yellos line for the initially excited state, being

replaced upon some experience by the ultimately occupied component ρfin, whose probabilities

are drawn in red. This process is then followed, after a delay of about one-tenth of a second, by

the acquisition of an awareness (consciousness) of the new neuronic state, with the respective

occupation probabilities drawn using a blue line which is horizontal initially and rises to one

finally, for before and after the acquisition of awareness. The cognitive delay 0.1s is in line with

the empirical observations,” the Libet delay” in Libet et al. (1983). As an outcome, the actual

state of consciousness is aligned with the actual neuronic state (i.e., identical in their respective

Hilbert-spaces).

THE COUPLING

At the backbone of the theory lies the role of the Lindbladian term, which primes each of the

stages I -IV, bringing about the transitions. The source of this term as arising from an interaction

between the neuronic framework and the surrounding is not identified at this stage, but seems

to reside in the unity of the neuronic system with its broad surrounding. Such unity has been

called into play for the interpretation of the quantum mechanical measurement process already

by N. Bohr (1958): ”The answer that we get is built up from the combined interaction of [the

observer’s] state and the object of interrogation.” and more recently in several works: Thus,

one may find from John Bell that ”The answer that we get is built up from the combined

interaction of [the observer’s] state and the object of interrogation.” (Bell (1990); from Asher

Peres ”A measurement both creates and records a property of the system” (Peres 1998), and

further by Anthony Leggett: ”...under these conditions (without the environment interaction)

the macroscopic apparatus, and more generally any part of the macro-world which has suffered

Page 10 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 38

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

Griffiths 2001). A further generalization in terms of an algorithmic information distance is due

to Chater and Vit ́anyi (2003).

Another remarkable development, also due to Shepard and summarized in Shepard (2004), is

that the time required to determine that two things are identical, in spite of their apparent

difference, linearly increases with their transformational separation (” distance”) in the space

of possible positions. On the other hand, the time required to determine that two things are

different, despite their apparent similarity, decreases non-linearly, as function of their

separation in the space of possible objects. As the guiding principle for clustering together in

human perception of widely different stimuli (sources of experience), Shepard (2001)

proposed that, ”[these] generally form a connected local region in the space of possible objects,

despite appreciable differences among individual objects of that kind in size, shape, position,

motion, or color”. We shall reformulate this broad” juxtaposition” idea of Shepard, originally

pertaining to some undefined space (his” appropriate representational space”) to apply to the

Hilbert spaces that constitute the basic elements of the present theory. Passing from a

continuous representation of different stimuli (as in rotationally different stimuli) to those that

differ in a discontinuous, discrete way, Shepard notes that one would still obtain an exponential

type of fall-off of generalization with distance, where distance is now defined in terms of the

sum of the weights of the features that differ between the two objects or, if the features are all

equal in weight, simply in terms of the number of differing features.

Noting the above two apparently discordant assertions by Shepard, [that the reaction time (RT)

for affirmative response increases linearly with distance, whereas on the contrary, the

discriminatory RT falls off according to a decreasing, non-linear function of distance between

stimuli in representational space], we shall now demonstrate how in the present formulation

of transitions the two findings may be reconciled.

As a preliminary, one bears in mind that quantitatively the RT differs by a so-called” response

time” from (it is less than) the actual experimental delay time (the time that has elapsed

between the presentation of the task to the subject and the instant of the subject giving his

decision). Then, for the explanation of affirmative responses, we simply utilize a protocol due

to Sternberg (Sternberg 1966), of which more later, which predicates that for a decision

involving several items, the system declares its decision after scanning all items, and not at any

interim stage, thereby resulting in a RT that is proportional to the number of items. If we now

conjecture that the distance in Shepard’s experiments is represented by the number of states

in the Hilbert spaces, the proportionality of RT to the distance follows for affirmative decisions.

When an affirmative answer is not forthcoming, as when the subject discriminates between the

presented and the task items, the decision time is composed of two times; the first, during which

the subject scans all the relevant items, as in the case of an affirmative decision, but now

reaching a negative result followed by a further search. Such a search had been investigated

some long time ago, e.g., for discriminating sounds as functions of both frequencies and

intensities. It was found, e.g., by Chocholle (1940), that the discrimination time decreases as

some inverse power of the sound intensity, with the exponent varying between −0.50 and −0.25

(with a dependence on the sound frequencies). Other experiments (both pre-dating and post- dating Chocholle’s), including also those with light, gave similar results. A detailed theoretical

Page 11 of 18

39

Englman, R., & Yahalom, A. (2024). A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness; Memory Experiments. European Journal of Applied Sciences,

Vol - 12(3). 29-46.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/aivp.123.16966

study (Luce and Green 1972) interpreted the stage of decision making by the neural system as

one at which the incoming pulse-signals in the brain reach some saturation. A stochastically

varying mode was analyzed which then in some limiting approximation led to the result for the

mean reaction time:

RT = 2 arrival time of the signals/Sound intensity (6)

The intuitive meaning of the result, derived by the authors of (Luce and Green 1972) is that

when the intensity is large, proportionately less time is needed to saturate the system with

information. The inverse power relation in the above expression is to be noted, agreeing with

the empirical findings.

In a further series of studies of the latency time of short-term memory, pioneered by S.

Sternberg (1966), subjects were first given a set of terms or symbols and then tested by a

further term or symbol, and asked whether or not this was one of the test terms? Remarkably,

their mean reaction time (RT) increased linearly with the length of the sequence. The linearity

and slope of the reaction time was hypothesized by the author as implying the existence of an

internal serial-comparison process with an average rate of 25-30 symbols per second. Similar

rates were found for positive and negative answers by the subjects, which finding led the author

to his theory that in short-term memory experiments the subject scans all preliminarily

presented items, before making a response. Subsequently, some discrepancies from linearity

were noted, e.g., when the experiments were repeated with differing ordering of the test terms,

as in Derosa and Morin (1970), with Sternberg (2016) replying with a vigorous defence of his

position.

THEORETICAL

Short-Term Recall Experiments

Saul Sternberg’s serial exhaustive scanning paradigm, proposed for the explanation of short -

term memory experiments reconciling positive and negative responses, implies an information

transfer between that part of the collectives of neuronal states which was created by the pre- presented items and the consciousness state in the brain that elicits the response. Formally, in

the dual Hilbert space model, this may be represented in the most transparent way in terms of

a coupling between the neural and consciousness spaces through interaction terms in the

Hamiltonian, written in a second quantization description, in the form, nin†

jcic

j for which the

letters and their daggered version in n,n†,c,c† represent respectively destruction and creation

operators in the neuronic and consciousness Hilbert spaces. In physical terms, the information

transfer is affected by some further entities, whose nature is not known as of now, these being

the cognitive counterparts of mRNA featuring in the central dogma of biology for the formation

of peptides from DNA. In this the translational elongation is achieved through the scanning of

the full length of mRNA by the ribosome, this being done at a rate of about 1.5 codon per second

(Heinrich and Rapoport 1980). It stands to reason that through some entities Nature employs

the same stratagem for the analogous scanning in the brain for the information transfer, this

being done at a rate of items per second higher by a factor of about 20. (The factor is likely due

to the correspondingly higher complexity along a linear dimension in the brain, in comparison

to other bodily organs.)

Page 12 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 40

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

Long-Term Memory Results

By the time that the recall experimentation takes place at some instant after the short-term

memory times (this being of the order of 10ms), as in the Shepard type of investigations of

identification or discrimination between tests and probe items, the neuronic wave functions

have changed their character, due to the decohering interaction with the environment, from the

coherent entangled form of the foregoing section, to mixed quantum states. These are now

subject to a diffusive process, whose time dependent occupation probability was given in Eq.

[13] of Shepard (1958) as function of the distance Dik = |xi − xk| between test and probe items

and of time t by the Gaussian

(7)

in which V is a diffusion constant. A convolution integration is then shown by Shepard (1987)

to lead to a negative exponential dependence of the time integrated probability for the

affirmative identification between the test and probe items as function of their distance. This

establishes the theoretical basis of Shepard’s ”Universal Law of Generalization”.

The foregoing Gaussian (modified, as described below) is now proposed as the criterion for the

time (RT)-distance relation found in identification discrimination experiments (resulting in

positive-negative response, respectively), distance being a measure of dissimilarity between

sample and probe. For a qualitative understanding one notes that in a diffusion process along

an infinite line (and similarly for higher dimensions) starting at the origin, the occupation

probability at some distance away at first increases, as the diffuser makes its way randomly

away from the origin to this point, but then decreases as the diffuser proceeds to farther away.

It is now postulated that as the growing occupation probability exceeds a certain significantly

large critical value (to be denoted p0, meaning that Pr−>p0+0) a recognition is attained and

likewise when it later again decreases to beyond a critical small value p1 (which is different

from the former critical value) of the occupation probability, Pr−>p1−0 a discrimination

(negative response) has come into force. In the dual Hilbert space model of this article, the

diffusive motion takes place among the locations of the states in the neural function space, with

the consciousness’ Hilbert space” contacted”, aligned whenever the critical occupation values

are in place. To account for the empirical finding that the reaction time (RT) for affirmative

response increases linearly with distance, whereas on the contrary, the discriminatory RT falls

off according to a decreasing, concave-upward function of distance between stimuli in

representational space, we hypothesize a time dependent diffusion parameter V (t) in Shepard’s

Gaussian probability function, replacing his constant V. This assumed variable diffusion

parameter is such that the width of the Gaussian, instead of steadily increasing as in standard

diffusion theories, first increases and then drops off. The physical meaning of this is that the

basic diffusion step is not constant, but rather diminishes as the scanning proceeds. Variable

diffusion steps of a different kind are known as Levy-walks.

Examples of the postulated widths are depicted in Figure 2. Algebraically they take the form:

(8)

Page 13 of 18

41

Englman, R., & Yahalom, A. (2024). A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness; Memory Experiments. European Journal of Applied Sciences,

Vol - 12(3). 29-46.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/aivp.123.16966

Figure 2. Postulated root - mean -square - width in diffusion as function of time in milliseconds.

Parameters in Eq. 8 are as follows. Blue: t0 =0.05; Red: t0 = 0.1.

Figure 3. Early reaction times in milliseconds for confirmation. Blue: p0 (critical probability

density) = 0.5, t0 = 2; Red: p0 =0.1, t0 = 8. A linear relation is shown with broken lines for

comparison.

Affirmative answers for identifying probes slightly dissimilar from samples take place when

the diffusional probability reaches a critical value p0. The two curves in figure 3, with the

choices p0 = 0.5 in blue and p0 = 1 in red show reaction times (RT) in milliseconds, as function

of distance. A linear relation is shown with a broken line. At a contrary extreme of large

dissimilarities, the RT for discrimination takes large values. These are shown in figure 4, again

with two choices of the p1 criterion, p1 = 0.5, and 0.1 meaning that when the diffusive occupation

probability decreases down to this value, the subject concludes that there is no similarity. Due

to the time dependent Width, this discriminatory RT falls off according to a decreasing,

concave-upward function of distance between stimuli and probe in representational space, as

found empirically by Shepard (1987). Qualitatively, the curves are robust in both parameters,

p1 and t0.

0 10 20 30 40

time

0.5

1.0

1.5

2.0

2.5

3.0

Width

0.00 0.05 0.10 0.15 0.20

distance

0.2

0.4

0.6

0.8

Page 14 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 42

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

Figure 4. Reaction times for discrimination. Parameters: p1(critical probability density) = 0.05, t0

= 2 (blue); p1 = 0.1, t0 = 8 (red). An inverse power of distance curve is shown by broken lines for

comparison.

CONCLUSION

Mental states are postulated to be represented by quantum states, thereby constituting a

Hilbert space of their own, distinct from the physical Hilbert-space of the neural network but

being a mirror image (dual) of the latter. Thus, any actual mental state is at any time in

correspondence with (aligned to) a neural state, this being a particular vector in the neural

Hilbert space. The neural space is under perennial development under external experiences,

such that out of the multitude of initially disordered neuronic set of states ordered, coherent

neuronic sets are formed, one at a time, for each external stimulus. Then the states of mental

awareness (consciousness) are associated with alignment to the ordered neuronic quantum

states. Changes in both the neuronic and mental states are affected by a Gorini-Kossakowski- Sudarshan-Lindblad formalism, originally formulated to describe changes (dissipations) of

quantum systems induced by a macroscopic environment. Several components in the

postulated theory (as e.g., the quantum formulation of mental states, the transition to ordered

neuronic sets) are based on experimental evidence, as documented by the publications (and

quotes) cited in this article, but their sewing together as attempted here to represent generic

mental processes as fully quantum-like is novel, and requires factual confirmation.

Two kinds of memory experiments, for short- and long-term memory recalls, had led S.

Sternberg and R. N. Shepard, respectively, to semi-quantitative descriptions regarding

cognitive processes in the brain. These are interpreted within the dual Hilbert space model of

this paper, coupled with a proposal of a copying process analogous to the DNA-to-peptide

translation in biology and, further, through a diffusive process with time variant decrease of the

diffusion parameter. The latter leads to an experimentally verifiable prediction of a time

asymptotic narrowing of the probability-distribution of recalls.

0.5 1.0 1.5 2.0

distance

100

200

300

400

500

RT

Page 15 of 18

43

Englman, R., & Yahalom, A. (2024). A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness; Memory Experiments. European Journal of Applied Sciences,

Vol - 12(3). 29-46.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/aivp.123.16966

References

Aerts, D., Aerts Argu’elles, J., Beltran, L., Geriente1, S., Sassoli de Bianchi1, M., Sozzo, S. and Veloz, T. (2019)

Quantum entanglement in physical and cognitive systems: A conceptual analysis and a general representation.

European Phys. J. Plus 134, Article 493, pp.1-20; DOI 1019-12987-00.1140/epjp/i2

Amit, D, J., Modeling Brain Function, The world of neural networks, (University Press, Cambridge UK) ISBN 0-521-

36100-1

Asano, M., Ohaya, M.,Tanaka, Y., Basieva, I. and Khrennikov, A. (2011) Quantum-like model of brain’s functioning:

Decision making from decoherence. J. Theoretical Biol. 281pp.56-64.

Asano, M., Ohya, M., Tanaka, Y. and I. Basieva,I.(2012) On application of Gorini-Kossakowski-Sudarshan-Lindblad

equation in Cognitive Psychology. Open Systems & Information Dynamics 18(1)pp. 55-69 .

Atkinson, S., ed. (2011) The Philosophy Book (DK Publisher Dorling Kindersley, London) p. 227

Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, U.K.)

Barra, F. and Liedo, C. (2018) The smallest absorption refrigerator: The thermodynamics of a system with quantum

local detailed balance. European Journal of Physics Special Topics 231-246.

Bell, J. (1990) Against measurements. Physics World, 3 pp.33-41.

Block, N. (2009) Comparing the major theories of consciousness, in M. Cazzaniga, ed. The Cognitive Neuroscience

(MIT press, Cambridge MA) pp.111122.

Bohr, N. (1958) Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. (Wiley, New York).

Bruckmaier, G., Krauss, S., Binder, K., Hilbert, S. and Brunner, M. (2021) Tversky and Kahneman’s cognitive

illusions: Who can solve them, and why?

Front. Psychol., Article 584689, pp.1-23 (2021); doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2021.584689, pp. 1-23

Busemeyer, J.R. and Bruza, P.D. (2012) Quantum Models of Cognition and Decision. (Cambridge University Press,

Cambridge UK).

Chocholle, R. (1940) Variations ds temps de r ́eactions audits en fonction de l’intensit’e a diverse frequences.

L’Ann ́ee Psychologique 41 pp.65-124

Dehaene, S. and Nacache, L. (2001) Towards a cognitive science of consciousness: basic evidence and a workspace

framework. Cognition 79 pp.1-37.

Englman, R. and Yahalom, A. (2023) A Lindbladian-induced alignment in Quantum measurements. Foundations of

Physics, 53 pp.9-31.

Evans, J.St.B.T. (2003) In two minds: Dual process accounts of reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7 pp.454-

459

Farthing, G. (1992) The Psychology of Consciousness. Prentice Hall, New York), ISBN 978-0-13-728668-3.

Gorini, V., Kossakowski, K. and Sudarshan,E.C. G. (1976) Completely positive dynamical semigroups of N-level

systems. J. Math. Phys. 17pp.821-5.

Grau-Moya, J., Kru ̈ger, M. and Braun, D.A. (2018) Non-equilibrium relations for bounded rational decision-making

in changing environments. Entropy, 20 pp.1-14.

Page 16 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 44

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

Greenbury, S. F., Schaper, S., Ahnert, S. E. and Loui, A.A. (2016) Correlations greatly increase mutational robustness

and can both reduce and enhance evolvability. PLOS Computational Biology 12 e1004773.

Hameroff, S. and Penrose, R. (2014) Consciousness in the universe: A review of the ‘Orch OR’ theory. Physics of the

Life Reviews 11 (1) pp. 39-78.

Heinrich, R. and Rapaport, T.A. (1980) Mathematical modelling of translation of mRNA in Eucaryotes; Steady

states, time-dependent processes. J.

Theor. Biol. 86 pp.279-313.

Hu, H. and Wu, M. (2010) Landscape and Future Direction of Theoretical Experimental Quantum

Brain/Mind/Consciousness Research. Journal of Consciousness Exploration and Research 1 (8) pp.888-897.

Kahneman, D. (2013) Thinking, Fast and Slow. (Columbia, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, Columbia USA).

Khrennikov, A. and Asano, M. (2020) A Quantum-like model of Information processing in the brain. Applied

Sciences - Basel 10(2) pp.707-17, doi.org/10.3390/app10020707.

Khrennikov, A. (2019) Classical and quantum mechanics on information spaces with applications to cognitive,

psychological, social and anomalous phenomena. Foundations of Physics, 29 pp. 1065-98.

Kosloff, R. (2013) Quantum Thermodynamics: A dynamical viewpoint. Entropy 15 (12) pp. 2100-18;

ArXiv:1305.2268.

Lamme, V.A. (2006) Towards a true neuronic stance on consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 10 pp.494–501.

Leggett, A.J. (1980) Macroscopic quantum systems and the quantum theory of measurement. Suppl. Progress

Theor. Phys. 69, 80-96.

Levine, L. (1981) Materialism and Qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, LXIV (4) pp. 354-

361.

Libet, B., Gleason, C.A., Wright, E.W. and Pearl, D.K., 1983 Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of

cerebral activity (Readiness Potential) - The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106 (3) pp.623-

642; doi:10.1093/brain/106.3.623. PMID 664027

Lindblad, G. (1976) On the generators of quantum dynamical semigroups. Commun. Math. Phys., 48 pp. 112-30.

Link, M. (2022) Everything and more: the prospects of whole brain simulation, J. Philosophy 1908 pp. 444-459.

Low, P. (2012) The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness, Ed. J. Panksepp et al.

Luce, R. D. and Green, D. M. (1972) A neural timing theory for response times and the psychophysics of intensity.

Psychological Review 79 pp. 14-57.

Marx, K. (1867)” ...the life processes of definitive individuals, as they are in reality, acting and materially

producing.” Das Kapital: Kritik der politischen Oekonomie. Hamburg: Verlag von Otto Meissner, ETH-Bibliothek

Zürich, Rar 6494, doi.org/10.3931/e-rara-25622.

Moreira-Almeida, A, de F. Araujo, S. and Cloninger C.R. (2018) The presentation of the mind-brain problem in

leading psychiatry journals. Braz. J. Psychiatry, 43(3) pp.35-42.

Nagel, T. (2012) Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly

False. (Oxford University, Oxford,2012) p.35.

Page 17 of 18

45

Englman, R., & Yahalom, A. (2024). A Dual Hilbert-space Formalism for Consciousness; Memory Experiments. European Journal of Applied Sciences,

Vol - 12(3). 29-46.

URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.14738/aivp.123.16966

NEB (1980) New Encyclopaedia Britannica. 3 p.251.

Pearle, P., (2012) Simple derivation of the Lindblad equation. European Journal of Physics, 33(4), 805-22.

Peres, A. (1988) Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. (Kluwer Academic, Norwell MA).

Pothos, E.M. and Busemeyer, J.R. (2013) Can quantum probability provide a new direction for cognitive modelling?

Behav. Brain. Sci. 36 pp. 255-274

Rivas, A. and Huelga, S. F. (2012) Open quantum systems. An introduction, ArXiv:104.5242v2 9Feb2012 pp. 1-100.

Pothos, E.M. and Busemeyer, J.R. (2013) Can quantum probability provide a new direction for cognitive modelling?

Behav. Brain. Sci. 36 pp. 255-274

Rivas, A. and Huelga, S. F. (2012) Open quantum systems. An introduction. ArXiv:104.5242v2 9Feb2012 pp. 1-100.

Rosenthal, D. (2005) Consciousness and Mind. (Oxford University Press, N.Y.)

Rotondo, P., Marcuzzi, M., Garrahan, J.P., I. Lesanovsky, and M Müller (2018) Open quantum generalisation of

hopfield neural networks. J. Phys. A: Math. Theor., 51 115301.

Sappington, A. and Mohanty, V. (2023) Probabilistic genotype-phenotype maps reveal mutational robustness of

RNA folding, spin glasses, and quantum circuits. ArXiv:2301.01847 (05 Jan 2023)

Schneidman, E., Bery II, M.J., Segev, R. and Bialek, W. (2006) Weak pairwise correlations imply strongly correlated

network states in a neural population. Nature 440 pp. 2007-201.

Seth, A.K. and Bayne, T. (2012) Theories of consciousness. Nature Rev. Neuroscience 23 pp. 439-455.

Shepard, R. N. (1958) Stimulus and response generalization: Deduction of the generalization gradient from a trace

model. Psychological Review, 65 (4) pp. 242–256. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0043083

Shepard, R.N. (1987) Towards a universal law of generalization for psychological science. Science 237 pp. 1317-

1323.

Shepard, R.N. (2001) Perceptual-cognitive universals as reflections of the world. Behavioural and Brain Sciences.

24 pp. 712-748. DOI: 10.1017/S0140525X01000085

Shepard, R.N. (2001) On the possibility of universal mental laws: A reply to my critics. pp. 71 Behavioural and

Brain Sciences. 24 2-748.DOI: 10.1017/S0140525X01000085

Shepard, R.N. (2004) How a cognitive psychologist came to seek universal laws. Psychonomic Bulletin Review. 11

(1) pp.1–23 doi:10.3758/BF03206455.

Sloman, S.A. (1996) The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin pp. 119 3-22.

Sternberg, S. (1966) High-Speed scanning in human memory. Science 153 pp.652-654.

Sternberg S. (1969). Memory-scanning: Mental processes revealed by reaction time experiments. American

Scientist, 57, 421–457.

Sternberg, S. (1975) Memory scanning: new findings and current controversies. Quart. J. Exp. Psychol. 27 pp.1-32.

DOI: 10.1080/146407.

Sternberg, S. (2011) Modular processes in mind and brain. Cognitive Neuropsychology 28 pp.156-208, PMID

22185235 DOI: 10.1080/02643294.2011.557231.

Page 18 of 18

Services for Science and Education – United Kingdom 46

European Journal of Applied Sciences (EJAS) Vol. 12, Issue 3, June-2024

Sternberg, S. (2016) In defence of high-speed memory scanning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology

69(10) pp. 2020-2075.

Tenenbaum, J.B. and Griffiths, T.L. (2001) Generalization, similarity, and Bayesian inference. Behavioural and

Brain Sciences 24 pp. 629-40.

Tkaˇcik, G., Marre, O., Amodei, D., Schneidman, E., Bialek, W. and. Berry II, M.J. (2014) Searching for collective

behaviour in a large network of sensory neurons. PLoS Comput Biol. Jan.2014(10):1

Tononi, G. and Edelman, G.M. (1998) Consciousness and complexity. Science 282 (5395) pp. 1846-51, doi:

10.1126/science.282.5395.1846.

Tversky A. and Kahneman, D. (1983) Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability

judgment. Psychol. Rev. 90 pp.293–315, doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.90.4.293

Wang, D. et al. (2013) The potential of using quantum theory to build models of cognition. Topics Cogn. Sci. 5

pp.672-688.

Wigner, E.P. (1961) Remarks on the mind-body question, in A Scientist speculates, An anthology on partly baked

ideas. (Heinemann, London).

Zurek, W.H. (1991) Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical. Physics Today, October 1991, pp.36-

44

Zurek, W. (2014) Quantum Darwinism, classical reality, and the randomness of quantum jumps. Physics Today,

October 2014, 67 pp.44-50.

Zurek, W. H. (2022) Quantum theory of the classical: Einselection, Quantum Darwinism and Extantons. Entropy

24 (11) pp. 1529-1618, doi.org/10.390/e24111